The morality of destroying human embryos for the benefit of others is the main argument in both secular and religious bioethics. Opinions regarding the ontological status of preimplantation embryos vary widely. Some hold the
"conceptionalist" view, according to which the embryo is a "person", considering its potential to develop into a person. Others believe that the embryo (and even the fetus) is a "non-person", and that it ought not to be
attributed much, if any, moral status (DeWert & Mummery, 2003).
There is another viewpoint of the "relative value" of human embryos, more than cells but
less than persons (Hinman, 2009). This view states that embryos deserve respect but not to the same extent as a fully developed person. According to this moral argument, the moral status of a human embryo gradually increases through its development in the uterus, and at
the point of birth it is entitled to enjoy full
rights
of human
beings
(United Nations Educational, Scientific and Cultural Organization, 2004).
Another moral argument states that the status of embryos differs across milestones in the
process of embryonic development (United Nations
Educational, Scientific and Cultural Organization, 2004). In this argument, the question is at what point after fertilization of egg by sperm the cell mass becomes a human
being. This seems an ethical impasse which science may not be able to resolve. For ethical decision making on stem cell research, we should determine when a new human entity comes into existence. According to the scientific facts, there are significant points for delineation of human embryos, including: the moment of fertilization, the point of implantation in the uterus, the initial appearance of the primitive streak (19 days), the beginning of heartbeat (23 days), the development of brain waves (48 days), the point at which essential internal and external structures are complete (56 days), the point at which the fetus begins to move (12-13 weeks) (Hinman, 2009), and the point when the foetus would be viable outside the uterus (Balint, 2001).
As mentioned above, during the third week of human embryo development, the primitive
streak develops and three germ layers appear. Before this stage, embryos can
split and produce two or more embryos; however, after development of the
primitive streak, the
embryo is a unique entity. In view of this fact, many believe that ontological individuality
starts at this point, hence the embryo can be used for research prior to this stage; up to 14
days of development (DeWert & Mummery, 2003).
Religious schools also make various points which will be discussed later. There is no doubt
that an embryo is a living being whether or not it merits human rights. However, an entity
would have the full rights and privileges of human
beings when personhood begins.
There are different views on preimplantation embryos. Some bioethicists suggested "the
trajectory argument"
to defend
the human rights of a human embryo before implantation (Hinman, 2009).
According to this argument, since an early embryo has the potential to be a
human being in the future, it deserves protection. However, others claim that an entity
before implantation is no more than a seed. There is also another viewpoint, according to
which human embryos, even if they are not persons, deserve respect (Hinman, 2009). As
Hinman (2009, slide 20) concludes: "We can see some advocates of both sides of the hESCdebate as accepting the
general
principle
of respect
for innocent
human life; their
disagreement
may not be over the principle, but
over the way
in which the principle
is to be applied
in particular cases."
The fear of "instrumentalization" of human embryos is a barrier to create embryos (DeWert
& Mummery, 2003). However, despite opposition to creation of embryos for research, there
are arguments in support of the use of spare embryos in the process of IVF as sources of embryonic stem cells because such embryos would be destroyed anyway. Several hundred
thousands of unwanted embryos are discarded annually in IVF clinics. The use of such
embryos before the appearance of the primitive streak is supported by
many ethicists. However, as stem cells that are derived from surplus embryos may cause immune rejection when transplanted to a patient, some researchers emphasize the production of genetically identical stem cells by the use of cloning or other techniques in order to avoid immune rejection in transplantation (United Nations Educational, Scientific and Cultural Organization, 2004).
The research carried out in Canada (Zarzeczny & Caulfield, 2009) shows that even though
issues
related to the moral
status of embryos
continue to
be a main issue
in the literature on
stem cell research, discourses associated with the moral status of embryos may not receive
the same attention in social
and other realms.
For instance,
while the
moral status
of embryos has a central role in legal discourse, it plays a relatively minor role in print media
(Zarzeczny & Caulfield, 2009).
0 comments:
Post a Comment